AS 201 More on Confucianism

1. Confucian philosophy emphasizes self-development, both in terms of:


--(i) academic study that trains the intellect, requires discipline and restraint, and that provides idealized models of virtuous rule (the Sage-Kings which are the wise rulers of the distant past), and


--(ii) moral and spiritual development which emphasizes and internalizes the virtues of character, and that is focused on becoming Junzi (君子), the "Exemplary Person," that is the ideal or "realized" Confucian person.

The nature of the "Exemplary Person," the Junzi (君子), aka the noble or superior man, is like the wind, the nature of the inferior man(小人, the small man, the petty man) is like the grass. When the wind blows over the grass, it always bends.

(君子之德風。小人之德草。草上之風必偃)

2. Confucianism was institutionalized through a system of education and examination that was a necessary requirement for public officials. The examination system increased the level of competence of the officials, created a shared national culture, and opened the ranks of governments, in principle and often in practice, to all classes of society. Academic study thus becomes a clear path to social advancements, and it was also valued in-itself as essential to becoming a Junzi, the ideal or "exemplary" person.

3. Good government essentially involves promoting and maintaining social harmony. The key to social harmony is the discernment and wisdom of rulers in designing the social institutions that encourage the natural virtues of the people.


Therefore, Confucian morality includes all of the customs, manners, habits, conventions, and indeed all of the ordinary behavior of daily life. In Confucian philosophy this is characterized as the following of Li (), which is protocol, etiquette, propriety, and ritual. Most simply, Liis simply acting in accordance with conventionally recognized right behavior. Following Li involves self-discipline, inner calm, and an internalization of good habits. Acting rightly is not always easy and indeed can often require discernment.  Li, of course, also includes the appropriate behaviors of rulers and subjects, and thus the principles of good government and citizenship. An interesting and related Confucian doctrine is the Rectification of Names: “Let the ruler be a ruler, the subject a subject, the father a father, the son a son” and the state will also be well order (Analects 12:11).

Persons who manifest Li fulfill their role specific responsibilities and display characteristic virtues. A teacher, for example, has a specific role which includes distinct responsibilities and excellences of character, and students also have specific responsibilities and distinct virtues. When students and teachers both realize their natures, when each is what it is, the class is harmonious and successful. We must each be what we are, for society to flourish.

4. The other Prime Virtue of Confucian thought is Ren (or Jen, 仁), which is often thought of as benevolence and humaneness; sometimes, "goodness" or "humanity," but also can be rendered as "authoritative conduct." The cultivation of Ren is essential to human virtue and excellence and it is what individual cultivate in themselves if they consider themselves to be following a pathway, the Way or the Dao (道).

Ren and Li are intimately connected: Ren as humanness and benevolence--authoritative conduct--guides and shapes social conventions and the principles of propriety (or Li); and, on the other hand, Ren as humanness/benevolence, in one’s dealings with others, is only realized through all of the daily practices and rituals of life--Li ().

Li () is blind without Ren, and Ren (仁) is empty without Li.

Closely related to Ren (humanness/benevolence) is the Confucian principle of Reciprocity (). We have already seen that proper social relations involve mutual benefit. Indeed, like all of the major religious traditions, Confucians have a version of the “golden rule": “What you do not want done to others, do not do to others.” It is interesting that the principle is not focused on one’s self but on what one does not want done to others, and here we perhaps see a deeply relational, non-individualistic element in Confucian thought--treat others as you would want them to treat you.

In the Analects, 7.34, Confucius says that he cannot be considered a Sage, shengren, 聖 人 and in 7.26 he laments, ‘I have no hopes of meeting a sage. I would be content if I would meet someone who is a junzi 君子.’  The junzi holds ‘the words of the sage’—along with the Mandate of Heaven and great men—‘in awe’ (16:8). The sage is the one person who ‘can listen to music and discern in it the original details and quality of an age and its culture’ (Hall and Ames).

Ignoring the words of their Master, the Confucian tradition soon designated Confucius a sage, indeed, it viewed him as the archetypal sage. Hall and Ames further fill out the portrait of the sage as ‘the rare person [who] elevates the human experience to profound aesthetic and religious refinement, making the human being a worthy partner with the heavens and the earth.’ Moreover, and in keeping with the metaphorical imagery of dao, ‘the shengren have traveled, appropriated and enlarged a longer stretch of the road than the shi 士 (knight, later scholar-official) and junzi, and they are providing signposts and bearings for the latter as well.’
- See more at: http://www.religiousleftlaw.com/2011/04/the-confucian-worldview-a-rational-reconstruction.html#sthash.RnWYhibP.dpuf

There could be a perception the Ren is the good, more Daoistic side of Confucianism, and Li is the more rigid or less exciting side. However, we should also consider that the way the two interact and reinforce each other. Ren and Li create a synergy and a dynamism. As stated above, Ren as humaneess and benevolence guide and shape social conventions and the principles of propriety (or Li); while, on the other hand, Ren as humanness/benevolence, in one’s dealings with others, is only realized through all of the daily practices and rituals of life. Li is blind without Ren, and Ren is empty without Li. Li provides the social forms in which the Raw, Personal Energy of Existence can be realized; once they are realized, a certain "Virtue" or Excellence" (De ) arises and this is what constitutes our Humanity, our Ren . When this kind De "Virtue" or "Excellence" (at becoming one's own person) appears it may manifest itself as a kind of "Charismatic" or even magical power that human beings can emanate.

And Li is not totally devoid of flexibility. Although the training through which virtues are acquired proceeds according to a general set of rules or principles, the actual decisions made by a person with fully virtuous dispositions are both more flexible and more authoritative than the rules themselves. Thus, once a practice has been mastered, in the sense that the requisite virtues have been developed, this mastery brings with it a certain independence from the rules that constitute the practice: the master is able to reflect upon the rules and may even chose to transgress or revise them if, in her best judgment, this is what is required to realize the good or goods specific to that practice. Practice and mastery thus bring with them a type of transcendence: the freedom to evaluate, criticize and seek to reform the practice tradition itself.  Someone who has acheived this master could be considered a person capable of manifesting Ren although Confucius did say that it was hard to find people who could actually do this! Li, then becomes not something static and rigid, but something spentaeous and effortless, something flowing and beautiful to behold. 

But we can safely say, and Fingarette is helpful here, that "Authoritative Conduct" or Ren resides in community, and community is rooted in inherited forms of life (we often call this tradition) which can be reproduced through the Imagery of Ceremony or Ritual/Li . Of course, ceremony is always communal and imbedded in our ceremonial practices, our Li ' if they are done correctly and are genuine or "right on," is a quiet Dignity and Power that is symbolic of all human relationships. So, society, and how we conduct ourselves in it, is a kind of cermonial performance in itself that is rooted in moral obligations, what we stand for and what we are supposed to do, what is appropriate or Yi (義) as in what is just, moral, fair, correct, and upright.

Closely related to Ren (humanness/benevolence) is the Confucian principle of Reciprocity (恕). We have already seen that proper social relations involve mutual benefit. Indeed, like all of the major religious traditions, Confucians have a version of the “golden rule:” “What you do not want done to others, do not do to others.” It is interesting that the principle is not focused on one’s self but on what one does not want done to others, and here we perhaps see a deeply relational, non-individualistic element in Confucian thought –treat others, as you would want them to treat others.

One could also say that Ren or Humaneness is the ultimate goal, is the larger vision, but it starts with filial piety. See this excerpt from the Analects:


Few of those who are filial sons and respectful brothers will show disrespect to superiors, and there has never been a man who is respectful to superiors and yet creates disorder. A junzi 君子, an "Exemplary Person," is devoted to the fundamentals, the Root. When the root is firmly established, the moral law will grow. Filial piety and brotherly respect are the root of humanity.


We all have some implicit awareness of the good or ren as a consequence of our enculturation and socialization through Li practices, and further Confucian self-cultivation draws us closer to ren as the essence of our humanity. If ren is ultimately rooted in the dao of tian, and we owe our existence to such cosmological forces and powers, it might even be argued, Socratic-like, that individuals possess an innate knowledge of ren, however dim, and that Confucian self-cultivation and education serves to bring such knowledge into ever-greater awareness and fruition, hence we are not ‘taught’ ren in the conventional sense. This is certainly in keeping with Mencius’ later assertion that human nature is intrinsically or innately good, accounting for how one can come to recognize and appreciate the good through psychological and moral developmental processes. It is traditionally argued that there are two indispensable parts to jen: shu (‘reciprocity,’ or the negative formulation of the Golden Rule: ‘do not impose on others what you yourself do not desire’) and zhong (loyalty). Empathy appears to be fundamental to both shu and zhong, and of course both can be no less appropriate to roughly equal relations as well.  

In the Analects, Confucius says:

The Ren Person (仁者), the "authoritative" and humane person, desiring to be established himself, seeks to establish others; desiring to succeed, s/he helps others to succeed. To judge others by what one knows of oneself is the method of achieving Ren or humanity...(6:30)

Confucius believed in the perfectibility of all people and he was against the idea that some humans are born superior to others. During his time it was held that nobility was a quality determined by status and that belonging to a specific social circle made a person morally superior. Confucius challenged this idea by saying that being morally superior had nothing to do with the blood, rather, it was a matter of character and personal development, a revolutionary concept at that time. And one could achieve this kind of moral superority through a program of self-cultivation and development that includes formal Education, the purpose of which should be to help one develop one's original ethical nature, one's character, one's native substance (質).  Such education is called self-cultivation, and it is only through such an education one achieves humaneness (仁).  A healthy emotional state of being helped one better grasp the proper ways to approach life, therefore to be constantly joyful was important. (Analects, 1:1)  Despite that the ultimate goal of Confucius was to serve in a government office, there were many passages where Confucius expressed joy and contentment at a life of learning and observation.  (Analects, 6:18; 6:21; 7:15; 7:18)


It seems that the formula that worked for Confucians was:


Description: peF.gif (3550 bytes)


In other words, you take a Person (人) and add actions that are "apprpriate" and "fitting" (義) given the circumstances, plus add the practice of "observing ritual propriety" (Li ) and from this potent and dynamic interaction can emerge Ren () or "morally authoritative conduct."

 

The Confucian concept of humaneness became the distinction of the cultivated person, or junzi 君子.   It transcended all social classes (15:38; 16:9) and became the basis of the future Chinese meritocratic system that replaced hereditary aristocratic rule.  Those who resisted education and self-cultivation, according to Confucius, should fall to the bottom of society.  But along with these "education-resistant people" that Confucius called the "small" or "petty" person (小人 xiaoren, literally, small people), women were permanently subordinate to men. (17:25) See this ecellent series of pages: http://www.friesian.com/confuci.htm

While definitions of Ren are hard to come by in the Analects, we can tease out some notions like:

 

1. Ren is the virtue of virtues; Confucius said he never really saw it fully expressed. The other virtues follow from it. He never gives and defends a definition of it although he does characterize it.

2. It is dearer than life itself--the man of jen will sacrifice his life to preserve jen, and conversely it is what makes life worth living.

3. Ren is a sense for the dignity of human life--a feeling of humanity towards others, self-esteem for yourself, and recognition that you are an "authoritative person ().

a. Such feeling applies to all humans--not just one nation or race. It is the foundation of all human relationships.

b. There is the belief that jen can be obtained; indeed, there is the belief in the natural perfectibility of human beings. Hence, he rejects the way of human action where one satisfies likes and avoids dislikes.

c. The first principle of Confucianism is to act according to jen: it is the ultimate guide to human action.

4. We should seek to extend jen to others.

 

Might we consider the following as possible interpretations:

1. People are only fully “human” to the degree that they are as sensitive to others' needs and human feelings as they are to their own. The perfectly human person Confucius called “humane,” using a word, “ren,” which was almost identical to the word for “person.”

2. The patterns of perfect humanity had been embroidered in the past by successive great Sages, inspired by Heaven, of whom the latest were the Zhou Dynasty founders. These heaven-ordained patterns constituted a complex set of social, political, and religious conventions and ceremonies known as “ritual,” or “Li.” These rituals of everyday and ceremonial conduct were no longer properly practiced in chaotic Eastern Zhou society--restoring these patterns of Chinese civilization was the practical path back to the ideal society.

3. Individuals should seek to recapture the patterns of Li (禮) in their own conduct. The best place to begin was in one's conduct towards one's parents.  Li were not isolated ceremonies to be practiced alone, but expressed the norms that were meant to govern all human relationships. Of these, the parent-child relationship was most basic; therefore, the first duty of every person was to act towards his or her parents in a perfectly filial manner.

4. Once a person had mastered the patterns of filial li in the role of the child, he or she would discover that the key to “humanity” (the virtue of ren) was the mastery of all the social roles that the human community needed him or her to play in a lifetime. The most basic of these roles were expressed as a set of Five Relationships: parent/child; elder/younger; ruler/subordinate; husband/wife; friend/friend. Once everyone understood and acted out the proper li for each social role they occupied, the world would be returned to order.

5. The person who had fully embodied Li and Ren would represent a superior type of ideal person--the fully realized human being.  Confucius referred to such a person by a special term: junzi (君子). This term originally had meant a “prince,” or person of high or noble birth.  For Confucius “princeliness” was a matter of moral attributes not of birth, and he pictured his perfected people as a new type of ethical aristocracy. In 7.34 Confucius says that he cannot be considered a shengren, 聖 人 and in 7.26 he laments, ‘I have no hopes of meeting a sage. I would be content if I would meet someone who is a junzi.’  The junzi (君子) holds ‘the words of the sage’—along with the Mandate of Heaven and great men—‘in awe’ (16.8). The sage is the one person who ‘can listen to music and discern in it the original details and quality of an age and its culture’ (Hall and Ames).

Hall and Ames further fill out the portrait of the sage as ‘the rare person [who] elevates the human experience to profound aesthetic and religious refinement, making the human being a worthy partner with the heavens and the earth.’ Moreover, and in keeping with the metaphorical imagery of dao, ‘the shengren have traveled, appropriated and enlarged a longer stretch of the road than the shi (士) and junzi (君子), and they are providing signposts and bearings for the latter as well.’


- See more at: http://www.religiousleftlaw.com/2011/04/the-confucian-worldview-a-rational-reconstruction.html#sthash.RnWYhibP.dpuf


Michael Nylan has nicely explained the egalitarian quality in the Confucian conception of Li as enshrined in the three Rites canons:


they promote a kind of egalitarianism in three senses: they assume that everyone can be perfected; they stipulate that a code of manners, aristocratic in origin, be learned by and applied to all humans; they advocate the assignment of social rank according to virtue and merit, defining both in terms of relative contributions to the larger society; and they aim to school each person, through theory and praxis, in the very social skills that facilitate effective interaction. Accordingly, it should come as no surprise that non-elites in early, medieval, and late imperial China were at times more eager than social and political elites to embrace the precepts set forth in the Rites canons.

 

 

 

Instructions